"(T)o say that the individual is culturally constituted has become a truism. . . . We assume, almost without question, that a self belongs to a specific cultural world much as it speaks a native language." James Clifford

The Natural Wealth Model of the Modern Corporation: A Basis for Sustainable Organization

This essay presents an alternative basis for the modern corporation. Theoretically at least, a company in line with this new paradigm should be devoid of greed because this foundation is in line with the notion of natural wealth, which, according to a few notable ancient Greco-Roman poets, does not incur avarice. I contend, moreover, that this alternative is fully compatible with the long-term viability of the modern corporation. To the extent that greed trips over itself, a business built on a paradigm designed to exclude greed can be expected to have an enhanced viability.

A lot of daylight separates how the “natural wealth” Greco-Roman poets viewed wealth and how it is typically thought of today.[i]  Cato exemplifies what the poets were so against. The strongest indication of his avaricious nature is that he wrote that man is most wonderful when he leaves more behind in his final accounting than he had inherited at birth.[ii] Wealth, in other words, is the most important thing. Had Cato simply earned enough income to meet his daily needs rather than invested his money to amass as much a surplus as he could, he might be spared the greedy epitaph, for he would have been closer to the poets’ ideal of natural wealth. Whereas it is limited to subsistence living, avaricious wealth is without limit because human desire, as distinct from needs, is limitless. This distinction—between limited and limitless—is vital to grasping the difference between the maximizing (or satisficing) profit model and one loosely based on natural wealth. Because such wealth is, strictly speaking, mythic in that it is of such an age, only the abstracted principle behind the descriptions of natural wealth can realistically be extracted and applied to a viable alternative model for the modern corporation. Put another way, our organizational artifacts are of a very different age than the mythic ideal of the Golden Age.

In their writings, Hesiod, Ovid, Virgil, Horace and Tibullus wrote the definitive mythic accounts of a once-golden age followed by successive ages of degradation.[iii]  These poets depict a pristine golden age of abundant food followed by successively degraded ages of injustice, avarice and struggle. Although the golden age is mythic, the latter ages reflect the urban moral corruption of the poets’ own day. The mythic ideal was for the Greeks and Romans the life under Knonos (Saturn) during the Golden Age.[iv] The Greeks tended to look back to a state of primal innocence. Plato, for instance, looked to the virtues of the Stone Age and Xenophon looked to the virtues of the early Persians. The Cynics sought a return to the simple life as against the social conventions of their time.[v]  Such utopias were less a sign of confidence in the future than of dissatisfaction with the present. 

The gradual accumulation of wealth in the early Roman Republic had brought about such ostentatious display and luxury that the Roman poets sought the simplicity of an earlier agrarian age.[vi] In the Roman culture of the poets’ own day, greed was thought to teach “arrogance, cruelty, neglect of the gods, and the belief that everything could be bought and sold.”[vii] Indeed, the word mercator, which is the root for merchant/trader, appears almost as a term of abuse during the time of the poets.[viii] For the Greek poets too, dissatisfaction with their time led them to contrast their own day with a golden age or lost paradise; that such a paradise could return in their cyclic framework did not overshadow their sense of basic pessimism.[ix]  Nevertheless, that such an ideal—albeit mythic in nature—was thought to be possible after their age suggests that we can apply it to our modern world.[x] The Golden Age is thus not like the Garden of Eden, for instance, which is an ideal of another realm that will not recur in another cycle.  

In Works and Days, Hesiod distinguishes five ages from the beginning of mankind, with the first being golden and the last—that of his own day—being the Iron Age, the most degraded of all the ages. The contrast here is between living a simple agrarian life and the urban licentiousness of luxury borne of wealth accumulated in excess of subsistence-level consumption.

The golden race “lived as if they were gods, their hearts free from all sorrow, by themselves, and without hard work or pain.”[xi]  Because the people were free from toil and grief, it seems reasonable to conclude that the golden race did not seek to accumulate, or stockpile, wealth for themselves beyond their daily consumption needs. Perhaps this is so because they had bountiful food, for “the fruitful grainland yielded its harvest to them of its own accord; this was great and abundant, while they at their pleasure quietly looked after their works.”[xii] The people looked after their own works, such as a small herd of livestock, suggesting that they did not produce and distribute goods to others.[xiii]

Hesiod states that pure spirits roamed the earth during the golden age, bestowing wealth on the golden race.[xiv] Such a notion of wealth is in stark contrast to that of the modern corporation. Indeed, there is no mention of merchants or firms existing in that ideal because the golden race could feast from the fruits of Nature directly.  “Pure spirits” acted as the distributors, and, according to Hesiod, the people looked after their own works, such as a small herd of livestock, suggesting that they did not produce and distribute goods to others.[xv]  It is not the sort of work that could become normative for a modern industrial economy.

Several Roman poets, such as Horace and Virgil, portray the golden age more realistically, however, akin to a primitive agricultural life. The Roman view of a Golden Age contains an idealized depiction of primitive rural life mixed in with the idyllic lost paradise.[xvi]  Qualities of ancestors associated with their simple lives were alluring as a solution to the social, economic and political revolution of the late Republic and early Augustan age. Such ancestral qualities, according to Horace, included “working the family field with his oxen,” “watching his flocks of bleating sheep,” and “pruning sterile twigs with his hook.”[xvii]  It would seem that natural wealth, like corporate wealth, is borne of labor. Horace writes in another passage of the Golden Age, however, as being without labor. “The earth unploughed produces yearly harvests, and vines unpruned are always in blossom!”[xviii]  An uneasy connection exists, therefore, between the primitive agrarian ideal of yesteryear and the utopia of the lost paradise wherein Saturn provides for the golden race. The ambiguity can be seen in Virgil’s work as well. 

Smolenaars clears up the confusion by pointing out that Virgil introduces the description of the “simple, laborious country life” in the Praise.[xix] This integration of labor and happiness in the farmer’s life is after the Golden Age during which Saturn does the work for the golden race.[xx]  “Like Aratus’ Dike, Virgil’s Saturn-Kronos, as ruler of his golden age (aureus), makes the earth produce food for the idle human beings.”[xxi] Accordingly, Virgil writes in Ecologue IV that in the Golden Age the vine will not suffer the pruning-hook or the fields the hoe in the Golden Age.[xxii] Elsewhere, he mentions grapes upon the unkept briar.[xxiii] He goes on to explicitly exclude investment and merchants. “The seafarer shall roam the wave no more, nor ships made merchandise.”[xxiv]  Horace, too, views happiness during the Golden Age as coming from being aloof from business, with no investment at all.[xxv] Cato would not have been at home in such an age.

Given the absence of labor, investment, and merchants during the Golden Age, the primitive agricultural motif only loosely applies. Even if the Golden Age of the Roman poets was an agricultural world supplied by the gods rather than through human effort, the Romans viewed the Golden Age as still attainable and realizable, “if only one abstracts oneself from the extravagance, desires and ambitions of urban life.”[xxvi]  Underlying natural wealth is the desire and ability to walk away from accumulating excessive wealth beyond one’s consumption needs; checking one’s ambitions, rather than a life without work, is that which the poets claim is attainable and realizable after the Iron Age.  So, rather than facing an external constraint in the form of a statute or supply limitation at their consumption level, the people of the Golden Age naturally cease their accumulating activity from within.  An internal force must constrain their unlimited desire for more.

The constraining motivation might be seen in Tibullus’s carefree life of rural poverty without the concerns associated with accumulated gold or excess cultivated land. That his life is ‘carefree’ signifies the absence of worries that would arise over stored up wealth;[xxvii] whether he labors or not to supply his modest needs is irrelevant here.  He wants to avoid the worries that go with accumulating wealth beyond that which he can consume. He wants to avoid the anxiety, which comes with ambition, epitomized by too much worry over one’s accumulated goods.  Tibullus would have felt quite out of place among modern business practitioners.

Besides a lack of worry, a stance against greed constrains members of the golden race internally.  For all of the poets surveyed here, the endless toil for ever-maximizing accumulations of wealth is to be avoided because it signifies avarice. It doesn’t matter whether greed is actually present; the behavior itself is indicative of excessive concern which in turn attests to greed. It follows that the poets viewed natural wealth in positive moral terms because did not contain the signs of avarice. Hesiod was undoubtedly thinking of this sort of natural wealth when he maintains that “shame goes with poverty” whereas “confidence goes with prosperity”—that with riches goes “nobility and honor.”[xxviii]  It would not be a sort of wealth gained by greed, because greed brings with it anxiety.  
 
A lack of both anxiety and greed coincide in natural wealth, owing to its orientation, or limitation, to satisfying subsistence needs.[xxix] In Boethius’ Consolation, for example, “(g)old, money, jewels and clothes are discussed and dismissed: nature provides what humans need for their sustenance, and everything over and above that is superfluous.”[xxx]  A simple life connotes living within nature’s means rather than having wealth as an accumulated surplus beyond what is needed for consumption; the result is happiness or contentment without a hint of greed. In Horace’s Odes, primitive tribesmen are said to live better than rich Romans, who seek riches by any means and are thus without virtue.[xxxi] The alien romantic world of easy-going carelessness about possessions is quite a contrast from wealthy Roman (or modern) materialism, which the poets drew on in depicting the most decadent stage, the Iron Age.

Unlike natural wealth, wealth in the Iron Age is infused with greed. Virgil refers to the greed of the Iron Age as a “lust for gain,” very close to Boethius’ “burning lust to possess.”[xxxii] Interesting, Augustine refers to his love for God in such terms.[xxxiii] Boethius portrays greed, which he defines as “the burning lust to possess,” in terms of “digging up heavy masses of hidden gold and gems longing to remain hidden, and is thus a feature of the ages past the golden age.”[xxxiv] Hesiod claims that greedy profit is “a kind of madness,” and that “by greed, a man’s shameless spirit tramples his sense of honor.”[xxxv]  The lust for immediate gratification may be behind Hesiod’s opposition to greed.[xxxvi] To quote from the Hymn of Callimachus, “Tyrants may seem happiest of men, but the poor sleep soundly at night. The man who sets a limit to his ambitions escapes worry and fear.”[xxxvii]

A limit to desiring more means a limit to the resulting wealth. In Metamorphoses, Ovid describes the iron race as suffering not only violence but also the “wicked greed for gain.”[xxxviii] The resulting wealth is “the spur of wickedness and sin.”[xxxix] That is to say, the resulting wealth triggers additional madness. Supporting the close link between Iron Age wealth and greed stressed by Ovid, Boethius and Virgil, Williams reads Horace as stating that wealth of the Iron Age leads not to happiness but “simply whets insatiable appetite for wealth.”[xl] Tibullus believed that accumulating gold and cultivated land causes ‘incessant dread of the approaching enemy’ and troubled sleep.[xli] 

The amount of the wealth (i.e., beyond natural wealth) is thus a direct indicator of greed; from the external, the internal (i.e., motivation) can be inferred. According to Kallet’s study on Thucydides, the vast accumulation of money, rather than how it is acquired or used, provoked the natural-wealth poets’ ire and moral condemnation.[xlii] Plutarch, for instance, ascribes avarice to Crassius not so much from by the way in which he had acquired his property, but by the size of it.[xliii] The aristocratic ideal of the poets' own day includes proper means and honorable ends for wealth.[xliv] Therefore, the poets did not assume the orientation of modern business ethics, which focuses on the proper sources and uses of wealth.

Today, the poets’ criticism would be based on the size of a firm’s earnings and retained earnings relative to what is needed for the firm to continue (i.e., sustenance) rather than become wealthier. Managers being hardly carefree, the poets would label them as greedy, and the surfeit corporate wealth as artificial rather than natural. The poets would classify both the excessive labor and surplus under the last age, the Iron Age, where “never by daytime will there be an end to hard work and pain.”[xlv] By implication, ceaseless profit-seeking is consistent with the greed of the Iron Age.

Propertius viewed money, which is absent in the Golden Age yet the object of such striving in the modern world, as the problem:

 “So you, then, Money, are the cause of our anguished lives!  Through you we travel an untimely road to death; you furnish cruel nourishment for men’s faults; from your head have sprung the seeds of woe.”[xlvi]

Given the possibility of disaster or theft, people of money fear the loss of what they have accumulated. Money is therefore hardly the sort of wealth that Hesiod praises as giving rise to confidence. All the angst in companies over money thus attests to wealth being artificial rather than natural—that is to say, of the Iron rather than the Golden Age. Part of the rationale for basing the modern corporation on natural rather than artificial wealth is thus to replace the anxiety and misery that greed causes with the contentment that is consistent with natural wealth. Accordingly, I turn now to constructing the alternative model, using ecological theory to render a natural-wealth basis applicable to modern business.


THE MODERN CORPORATION BASED ON NATURAL WEALTH AND ECOLOGY

In the Golden Age, nature provides enough resources such as food to satisfy human daily needs. Wealth is natural rather than accumulated—there being no need to stockpile because nature’s bounty is continuous. Put another way, wealth is kept within natural limits. Plutarch, for instance, describes the “riches that Nature requires” as being limited and confined within “the compass of their real needs, as within a circle drawn from a center at a certain distance.”[xlvii] Accumulating riches beyond what Nature provides intensifies the illness of greed such that it is “truly blind and deprived of light.”[xlviii] Because Nature provides for human sustenance, accumulating more would imply desire for more. The desire, being unlimited, is blind because it is unmoored from the limited nature of necessities. Put another way, stockpiling knows no upper bounds, especially if money that does not decay or diminish in its species is used.

Corporate retained earnings are accumulations of wealth. Revenue that is not needed to cover expenses goes into retained earnings. Because Nature does not provide, a portion of the accumulated wealth is necessary to cover expenses without which the company would not continue as a viable concern. To distinguish this portion and keep the retained earnings from surpassing it is, I contend, how the principle of natural wealth can realistically be applied to the modern corporation. Rather than being something to be maximized (less dividends), retained earnings is oriented to an equilibrium level. Corporate strategy under the premise of natural wealth rendered realistic is to be geared to reaching an equilibrium level of yearly revenue—enough to meet the firm’s consumption-needs for the year but no more. Equilibrium rather than more is the basis of this alternative model.

Because the golden race of the Golden Age maintains itself within a sort of natural equilibrium, individuals taking only what they need to meet their daily consumption-needs (because nature can be relied on), the metaphor of an ecosystem is a useful way to understand the alternative model of the modern corporation, especially as we have a natural inclination to construct our relationship with the surrounding world as a social reality in partially biological and ecological terms.[xlix] More to the point, an organization can be thought of as an ecological system, wherein forces being maximized press against various internal constraints that protect the viability of the organization itself. Simply by virtue of being a system, an organization acts as a constraint on forces within.

Ecological sustainability can explain how an organization can exist and flourish in the long run.[l] The ecosystem feature is the requirement that otherwise maximizing forces in an organization are legitimate up until the point that they bump up against the constraining force of the organization itself.  A company under ecological principles could pursue and accumulate profits only to a certain point, rather than without limit. Bring in the natural-wealth principle realistically applied and the upper bound is that which corresponds with expenses needed to be incurred for the company to continue. Greed is assumed to be obviated as long as the maximizing forces do not piece the “ecosystem” constraints that protect the viability of the system (i.e., the organization itself). Put another way, as long as profit-seeking is limited to meeting expenses that are necessary for the organization to continue rather than “grow,” business need not incur or involve greed.

I am not claiming that the carrying capacity of a business’s natural environment proffers sufficient constraint, for natural systems can accommodate stockpiling activities in excess of meeting basic operating needs.[li] Similarly, being ecologically sustainable—meaning that a firm can survive and profit in both its economic and natural environments—is not sufficient.[lii] A tighter constraint is needed to expunge greed because companies can exploit their natural environments in ways that externalizes (i.e., to third parties) the costs, while reaping revenue in excess of what is needed to keep the businesses in business for another year.

 Nor can we assume that industry-level constraints, such as industry self-regulation, and inter-industry pressures are sufficient. A variety of business ecosystems, each of which spans several industries, perforate through the modern world of business. Like its natural counterpart, a business ecosystem includes interdependent “species” (i.e., industries) and “members” (i.e., firms) that evolve in a reciprocal cycle in which changes in one species impact the process of natural selection for the other species.[liii] Within a business ecosystem, for instance, firms co-evolve capabilities around a new innovation. Interdependence, reciprocal cycles, co-evolution, and ecosystem-stability imply a potentially-constraining web-like structure that can potentially at least work as a constraint of the firms and even industries within. However, the accumulating of profit would not necessarily be constrained to consumption levels. For one thing, industry self-regulation can allow for quite a bit of “slippage” (i.e., mutually advantageous looking the other way). Moreover, several business-ecosystems may vie for dominance within a larger business environment. During such a phase, the constraints on accumulating activities would presumably decrease. 

Therefore, to hold motives maximizing accumulations down to a level oriented to sustenance-oriented consumption, constraints more powerful than those represented in the organization-environment constraints suggested by the ecological theories cited above are needed.  “Ecologizing” constraints capable of greater tightness in binding maximizing forces back are necessary such that an equilibrium level of revenue as well as retained earnings is achieved and maintained.

In the remainder of this essay, I discuss the ecologizing forces at the business-organization level as possible constraints on maximizing forces based in efficiency and power, respectively, inside. The same dynamic can be extended to the business-ecosystem level, though I do not cover it here. In discussing how organizational infrastructure can act as a semi-permeable membrane possibly containing intra-organizational forces that inherently resist being constrained, I draw heavily on Frederick’s theory on natural corporate management.

Frederick argues that potentially conflicting clusters of values pertaining to business and society derived from natural forces operate in businesses as well as between them and their respective business-environments.[liv] Each cluster comes out of “life-affecting processes,” and thus has a biological basis.[lv]  He claims that value-clusters pertaining to economy, power and technology exist within business, while ecologizing values are external to the firm, being based in the broader economic-natural ecosystem.[lvi]   I submit that an organization itself can act as an ecologizing force potentially constraining otherwise maximizing power-aggrandizing and economizing (i.e., efficiency) forces (see figure 1).

Economizing involves prudent actions that produce a net excess of outputs from a given amount of resources.[lvii] That is, economizing is oriented to “acting prudently and efficiently in using energy and matter, thus economizing, conserving, and sustaining those resources required for survival and material flourishing."[lviii] This value-cluster is oriented to maximizing the survival capability of the organism, in so far as economizing transforms resources into products of value for the organism’s survival. The maximizing tendency is inherent in economizing because the probability of a company’s survival can never be assured with certainty, so transforming resources into survival value never reaches a sufficient point. Like a squirrel not knowing for sure how long winter will be, a company’s management cannot have too many nuts stored—not counting dividends as the stockholders’ residual, and thus maximizing, claim (and thus value or force).

Power-aggrandizement values, which are geared to the acquisition, retention, and accumulation of power, have the same maximizing tendency.  Such values, and thus forces, are based on the forces in nature that are geared to dominance in a rank order or status hierarchy.[lix]  Frederick includes efforts toward a power-equilibrium, such as in the creation of an organizational structure solidifying status positions, as falling within this value-cluster.[lx] Viewing solidified status arrangements as if eddies on the side of a river’s main current, I contend that power-aggrandizing values are inherently expansionist, or maximizing, rather than seeking equilibrium.

Dominance behavior found in nature (including humans) has an inherent maximizing tendency because it is based on an animal’s continual status-dominance efforts to maximize its inclusive fitness (i.e. reproduction, or passing on genes as a broader goal).  An animal can never rest content with enough inclusive fitness because the probability of genes being passed on and surviving is never certain. So efforts to establish and maintain one’s status dominance must be continual; dominance must be continually maintained.  Hobbes puts for “a general inclination of all mankind, a perpetual and restless desire for Power after power, that ceaseth only in death,” because a human “cannot assure the power and means to live well, which he hath present, without the acquisition of more.”[lxi] Absolute power represents a quantity that can never be attained; hence power-aggrandizement is inherently a maximizing variable—a motive that can never truly be satisfied. 

Although Frederick points to the tensions between the economizing, power-aggrandizing and technologizing value-clusters within a business enterprise,[lxii] I submit that the three forces are more congruent and thus mutually supportive than they are at odds with each other because they all have the maximizing tendency; that is, they have the same basic underlying nature.  Because certainty of survival, security, or improvement can never be realized, economizing, power-aggrandizing, and technologizing efforts can never be sufficient. For instance, taking the resource-dependence, market power and innovation perspectives respectively, these value-clusters can be seen as being oriented to maximizing tangible short-run financials. 

In the language of systems theory, the three value-clusters, or forces, have a schizogenic nature.  A schizogenic system is not self-regulating because at least one variable within it seeks a maximal value (i.e., keeps on going) and is not held back by constraint either within the system or from the system itself.[lxiii] Because the variable is out of control, the system itself is in flux than able to re-establish equilibrium (i.e., a homeostatic steady-state). A natural ecosystem with a species maximizing itself, for instance, cannot maintain its equilibrium because the maximizing species pierces through the ecosystem, essentially puncturing it. Relatedly, increasing carbon-emissions can push the global climate beyond its long-held equilibrium, such that all bets are off on the survival of the maximizing species.

The fundamental tension in nature, including social organization, lies not in the tensions between the maximizing clusters, but, rather, between these and the ecologizing value-cluster that is of entirely (i.e., qualitatively) different nature. Ecologizing forces bring about and protect a dynamic equilibrium as well as steady-state homeostasis. In other words, such forces protect the viability of the whole by keeping the maximizing forces within from “piercing the envelop.” Ecologizing forces hold the system, whether an organism, social organization, or society/ecosystem, together (see figure 1).

Ecologizing values emphasize the value of interconnectedness or mutualism that exists within any system.[lxiv] They are based on natural forces operative in any natural ecosystem. Their character is found in the nature of an ecosystem qua ‘system’, as a system by definition constrains the forces within it. Absent a huge disturbance radically unlike those handled in the past, ecosystems are in “a state of homeostasis—that is, they are designed by evolution to be self-maintaining and self-regulating in order to achieve a stable long-term balance or dynamic equilibrium.”[lxv] Although ecosystems can grow or shrink, they are characterized by a basic long-term balance between the demands of a population and the environment.[lxvi] In fact, balance (of species and the environment) is integral to an ecosystem.

Systems theory can help to explain the functioning of an ecosystem in terms of its various forces. A homeostatic equilbrium can absorb a certain amount of disruption while staying at a steady-state without interrupting natural stability; and obviously then a dynamic equilibrium can too, as it grows or evolves.   A steady-state system contains systemic feedback loops which act to constrain the forces within the system. This holistic character to self-corrective systems permits balance and equilibrium.[lxvii] 

The complexity, or web-like quality, of an ecosystem tends to keep the population of each component at the level most appropriate for the smooth functioning of the ecosystem as a whole.[lxviii]  The checks and balances in the web-like structure of interdependence and environment-species ‘fit’ permit the ecosystem to be self-repairing, maintaining, and regulating by means of negative feedback; beyond certain limits, the expansion of a component gives rise to positive feedback which drives the system toward destruction until a new homeostatic balance can be maintained. 

Therefore, a key feature of an ecosystem is the ability of its web-like structure to constrain the growth of species within which would otherwise result in excessive production that the rest of the ecosystem could not tolerate given the existence of other limits which are relatively slow to adapt to the excessive growth.[lxix]  Limits are part of the web-like self-regulating process that leads to homeostasis and dynamic equilibrium.  In fact, limits are necessary for there to be any system at all. Were the species able to maximize without constraints in the environment (i.e., the ecosystem), which includes all the other species, we could hardly say that the different animals are part of a system.  No one species can grow indefinitely, maximizing itself and in the process displacing all other species, for this would destroy the system, and consequently, that which sustains even the species itself. 

The pervasiveness of negative-feedback controls in an ecologizing force can enforce a homeostatic or dynamic equilibrium; the limitations are built into the ecosystem’s structure itself.[lxx]  Whereas economizing and power-aggrandizing are irreversibly linear, the web-like mutuality characterizing the ecologizing forces of an ecosystem are circular or cyclical—hence the positive and negative feedback-controls. There is therefore an inherent tension within any given ecosystem between forces seeking a maximal value and those tending to maintain or tend toward equilibrium. 
Consider, for instance, the impact of the ecologizing force of cooperation, a manifestation of interdependence, in constraining power-dominance in human and other primate species. The moral sanctioning in egalitarian political arrangements can suppress the dominance behaviors by particular members.[lxxi] One scholar writes that “the capacity for purposeful and decisive collective action provides a cultural antidote to the domination tendencies of would-be alpha males that over the generations ensures that stronger individuals cannot establish despotic political styles or dynasties.”[lxxii] In the early 1960s, the tussle between key alpha-males in the U.S. and U.S.S.R. could have destroyed the global ecosystem, not to mention the species itself. 

Opposing value tendencies, such as sharing and cooperation on the one hand and domination on the other, come out of contrary impulses implanted by nature, which result in an unstable equilibrium.[lxxiii] Indeed, human nature itself is not monolithic but is the outcome of competing forces that commonly result in behavioral ambivalence. Nietzsche suggests that even thoughts are essentially instinctual urges that tussle for dominance—the idea that reaches the conscious mind is the most powerful instinct among those in contention. In short, a “psychology of balancing, contradictory tendencies” that play out in human nature and through human evolution can be thought of as ecologizing forces in that the balancing keeps our power-aggrandizing, economizing, and technologizing/innovating forces from destroying us and the ecosystems that sustains us as a species.[lxxiv]

That ecologizing forces can be seen in a human nature as well as in natural ecosystems is good evidence that such forces can be found along with the maximizing forces in human organizations as well as in business ecosystems. In other words, a company contains both maximizing and potentially constraining forces, and so do business systems, such as a financial system or an industry (i.e., a business ecosystem), which are comprised of (potentially maximizing) companies. Even though the scale changes step-wise, the dynamic of maximizing forces interacting with steady-state forces is the same. Ecologizing forces are enacted at the system's level of any system because they are inherent in that which makes a system a system, whereas economizing, power-aggrandizing and technologizing forces can be found at the level of a system’s constituent units. Certain components of a company can get out of hand, resulting in the firm’s destruction. Likewise, a company within a business ecosystem can get out of hand and ruin the ecosystem. In 2008, Dick Fuld’s power-aggrandizing and reckless over-economizing ruined Lehman Brothers and nearly caused the U.S. financial system to collapse. Clearly, Lehman’s institutional restrains were no match for the CEO’s appetite.

Some ecologists “suggest that individual organizations cannot become sustainable: Individual organizations simply contribute to the large system in which sustainability may or may not be achieved.”[lxxv] Frederick concludes that ecologizing forces must be external to the firm, at the business-ecosystem level, which contains firms and other organizations in society.[lxxvi] If so, the financial system let us down in 2008; to expect Lehman Brothers to have muzzled its CEO’s power-hungry greed would be unrealistic.
Nevertheless, organizations are themselves systems that are composed of component parts—namely, departments and human beings. Any organization contains an internal tension between its maximizing and constraining steady-state forces. Businesses bear the costs of integration in part so no department gets out of hand. Because those costs increase disproportionately as an organization gets larger, budget-cutters may enervate the central ecologizing force. Undoubtedly, AIG’s stockholders in 2008 must have regretted that the financial derivatives department in London had not been more closely integrated (and thus monitored). That this could have been done undermines the argument that ecologizing forces can exist only at the business-ecosystem level. A company itself can be thought of as an ecosystem.

For instance, valuing interdependence and cooperation normatively as well as in terms of the bottom line within a company could constrain profiteering by particular profit centers such that the departments work together to reach a common goal.  The value and a supporting firm-wide infrastructure of policies and procedures can operate as a systemic constraint on department heads. Such an infrastructure could be used to serve a goal of keeping the company in its homeostatic or dynamic equilibrium instead of maximizing profits. Such a use of ecologizing forces would be in line with the principles of natural wealth.



A NEW MODEL OF THE MODERN CORPORATION

Rather than as a ceaseless profit-seeking machine, a firm can be alternatively intended and designed as a system striving to maintain a homeostatic or dynamic equilibrium tied to its consumption needs, which remain constant or evolve, respectively, rather than expand exponentially or even without limit. Obviating the problems that go along with the distended hypertrophy of a component part of a business organization when maximization is valued, a fixation on holding to an equilibrium state may even enhance a firm’s long-term viability.

A natural ecosystem is sustained in a homeostatic steady-state, whereas its transformation into a schizogenic (i.e., maximizing) system leads it to destruction.  Frederick claims “steady-state economizing is a condition of homeostasis, in which the life unit simply maintains itself, staving off entropic tendencies”[lxxvii] This condition is more conducive to the survival of the organism than is limitless maximization because of the lack of stability in the latter.

Admittedly, a belief in growth even for its own sake dominates the modern-business mind, so it should not be surprising to find executives (and stockholders) esteeming economizing and power-aggrandizing values.[lxxviii] The reigning assumption that the lack of growth means death reckons equilibrium an admission of failure rather than a sustainable basis. Corporate wealth should be accumulated without limit, it is typically thought, or competitors will gain the upper hand by capturing more market-share. No thought is given to the possibility that the stability of equilibrium could enable attention to be focused on improving the product or service.

Put another way, intensification can replace maximization. Crucially, efforts to intensify within a static or dynamic equilibrium could not be so much as to threaten the equilibrium. Improved sales figures, for instance, would trigger increased dividends and/or days off rather than higher retained earnings, more investment, and ceaseless profit-seeking. A healthy equilibrium with some slack built-in as insurance against a market shock is consistent with the adage, work to live rather than live to work.  
    
Under this alternative model, profit would be sought up to the point at which consumptory expenditures, including investment in plant and equipment (including human resources) and dividends, can be met. Operating expenses, capital investments, and dividends would not surpass levels that are in line with the static or dynamic equilibrium, whether existing or planned. Dividends, for instance, would be constant (i.e., static equilibrium) or gradually increasing as the firm evolves (i.e., dynamic equilibrium).

Although Frederick maintains that ethical principles may function as ecologizing forces, I contend that an organization staving off the maximizing mentality would require internal constraints stronger than the normative value that greed is squalid.[lxxix] The CEO, as the leader of an organization, could evoke a vision that limits the accumulating activities to consumption needs. Shareholders could approve a charter amendment to the effect that profit would be pursued only to the extent to which a dynamic equilibrium could be maintained. Human resource policies, for example, could mandate more vacation-days as revenue approaches the equilibrium level.

In short, the ecologizing forces would need to have sufficient disproportional strength to outweigh the force of avarice in ceaseless profit-seeking and accumulating. At the point at which revenues hit the equilibrium-ecologizing level, a firm’s strategy would turn from gaining more revenue to maintaining the equilibrium. It is at this point that the alternative model really differs from the default model. 

Indeed, rather than viewing the modern corporation so much as a concentration of private wealth,  the emphasis would be on the corporation’s functioning as an exchange mechanism wherein resources pass through in a value-creating process that is in equilibrium within and beyond the organization in the larger system of business and society.



Figure 1


                            Ecologizing Model Adapted from Frederick (1995)




References

Bailey, D.R.S. (2002). (Ed. & Trans.). Letters to Quintus and Brutus; Letter
Fragments; Letter to Octavian; Invectives; Handbook of Electioneering. 
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an Ecology of Mind. New York: Ballantine.

Berger, P. and Luckmann, T. (1966). The Social Construction of Reality; A
Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.

Boehm, C. (1989) Ambivalence and Compromise in Human Nature. American
Anthropologist 91: 921-939.

Brazouski, A. (2000). The Elegiac components of the De Consolatione. Classica
Et Mediaevalia 51: 237-250.

Cicero, T. (1991) On Stoic Good and Evil: De Finibus Bonotum et Malorum
Liber III and Paradoxa Stoicorum. ( M. Wright, Trans.). Westminister, UK:
Aris & Phillips.

Dodds, E. R. (1973). The Ancient Concept of Progress. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Dracontius, B. A. (1914). Dracontii De Laudibus Dei, Satisfactio Romulea,
Orestis Tragoedia, Fragmenta, Incerti Aegriudo Perdicae. Lipsiae.

Earl, D. (1967) The Moral and Political Tradition of Rome. Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press.

Erdal, D, A. Whiten, C. Boehm, and B. Knauft (1994) On Human Egalitarianism:
An Evolutionary Product of Machiavellian Status Escalation? Current Anthropology 
35 (2): 175-183.

Frederick, W. C. (1992). Anchoring values in nature: Toward a theory of business
 ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly 2 (3): 283-304.

______________(1995). Values, Nature and Culture in the American
Corporation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

_____________ (1998) Creatures, Corporations, Communities, Chaos,
Complexity.  Business & Society 37 (4), 358-389.

_____________ (1999). An Appalachian Coda: The Core Values of Business.
Business & Society 38 (2), 206-211.


Hesiod (1959). The Works and Days. In R. Lattimore (Trans.)  Hesiod.
Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

Hobbes, T. (1996). Leviathan. Richard Tuck (Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.

Horace (1994). Odes and Epodes. David Mulroy (Trans.). Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.

James, W. (1890). Principles of Psychology. NY: Holt.

Jennings, P. D. & Zandbergen, P. A. (1995). Ecologically Sustainable
Organizations: An Institutional Approach. Academy of Management Review 20 (4), 
1015-1052.

Kallet, L. (2001) Money and the Corrosion of Power in Thucydides: The Sicilian
Expedition and Its Aftermath. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Kelly, W. K. (Ed.). (1884) Erotica: The Poems of Catullus and Tibullus and the
Vigil of Venus. London: George Bell and Sons.

Lamberton, R. (1988). Hesiod. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Langhorne, J. and Langhorne, W. (Ed.s & Trans.) (1893). Plutarch’s Lives of Nicias,
Crassus, Aratus & Theseus. London: Cassell.

Lewis, N. and Reinhold, M. (1951). Roman Civilization. Vol. 1. NY:
Columbia University Press.

Lovejoy, A. O. & Boas, G. (1965). Primitivism and Related Ideas in Antiquity.
NY: Octagon Books.

Migne, J.P. (Ed.). (1844-1864). Patrologia Latina. (221 Vol.s). Paris.

Moore, J. F. (1993). Predator and Prey: A New Ecology of Competition. Harvard
Business Review 71: 75-86.

O’Daly, G. (1991). The Poetry of Boethius. Chapel Hill: The University of North
Carolina Press.

Ophuls, W. (1977) Ecology and the Politics of Scarcity: Prologue to a Political
Theory of the Steady State. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.

Ovid. (1986). Metamorphoses. (A.D. Melville, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford
University Press.

Plutarch (1905). Plutarch’s Essays and Miscellanies. Vol. 2 ( A. Clough &
 W. Goodwin (Ed.s). NY: The Colonial Company.

Propertius (1990). Elegies. (G. P. Dodd, Ed. & Trans.). Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.

Rudd, N. and Powell, J.G.F. (1998). (Ed.s & Trans.). The Republic and The Laws.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Schmidheiny, S. (1992). Changing Course: A Global Business Perspective on
Development and the Environment.  Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Smolenaars, J.J.L. (1987). Labour in the Golden Age: A Unifying Theme in
Vergil’s Poems. Mnemosyne 40, 391-405.

Starik, M. and Rands, G. P. (1995)  Weaving an Integrated Web: Multilevel and
Multisystem Perspectives of Ecologically Sustainable Organizations. Academy of
Management Review  20(4): 908-935.

Virgil. (1951). The Aeneid of Virgil. (R. Humpharies, Trans.). NY: Scriber

_____ (1924). The Eclogues and Georgics of Virgil. ( T.F. Royds, Trans.). London:
J. M. Dent.

Williams, G. (1962). Poetry in the Moral Climate of Augustan Rome. Journal of
Roman Studies 52: 28-46.

Williams, G. (1968). Tradition and Originality in Roman Poetry. Oxford: The Clarindon
Press.

Worden, S. (2015) God’s Gold. Seattle: Amazon.




Endnotes

[i] In part, the shift in Christian thought from anti-wealth to pro-wealth (i.e., from associating wealth with greed to uncoupling the two) through the centuries accounts for this difference. See Worden (2015).
[ii] Lewis and Reinhold (1951):230.
[iii] O’Daly (1991).
[iv] Dodds (1973), p. 3
[v] Ibid.
[vi] Lewis and Reinhold (1951), p. 230f
[vii] Earl (1967), p.19.
[viii] Earl (1967). See Cicero, The Republic IV, 7, 7 in Rudd and Powell (1998); and Cicero, Brutus, 232 in Bailey(2002). Also, Plautus treats the commercial class with hostility and contempt, according to Earl (1967).
[ix] Dodd (1973)
[x] See Virgil: “The seafarer shall roam the wave no more, nor ships make merchandise: for all the earth shall be all-fruitful.”  Eclogue IV (lns 43-46), in Virgil (1924), p. 26.
[xi] Hesiod (1959), p. 31, lns 111-113
[xii] __________, p.33, lns 117-119
[xiii] See also Virgil, Eclogue IV (lns 43-46), in Virgil (1924), p. 26.
[xiv] Hesiod (1959), p.33
[xv] ______ (1959).
[xvi] O’Daly (1991), p. 180. See Virgil’s Fourth Eclogue and the Georgius, Horace’s Second and Sixteenth Epodes, Propertius 4.1, and Tibullus 1.3 and 2.5.
[xvii] Horace (1994), p.204.
[xviii] __________, p. 224, Epode 16, lns 43-44.
[xix] Smolenaars (1987), p. 394
[xx] ______________, p.397
[xxi] Ibid. See the Georgics 2.536ff.
[xxii] Virgil (1924), Eclogue 6, p.26.
[xxiii] _________, Eclogue 6, lns 32-33, p. 26.
[xxiv] _________, Eclogue 6, p. 26
[xxv] Horace (1994), p. 204, Epodes 2.
[xxvi] O’Daly (1991), p.182.
[xxvii] See Tibullus, Elegy 1, in Kelly (1884).
[xxviii] Hesiod (1959), p. 61 (lns 349-50), and p. 57 (lns 323-4).
[xxix] According to Brazouski (2000), the golden race lived simply but happily, and without greed, as indicated by Boethius’ Consolation and in Roman elegy. Boethius stresses the dangers of gold and gems, expensive dyed fabrics are spurned, men avoid extravagance and are not gluttonous.  Rather, they make proper use of the earth’s natural features and products for nourishment, shelter and refreshment, avoiding such perversions of natural products as wine mixed with honey. O’Daly (1991), p. 183.
[xxx] O’Daly (1991), p. 183, 2.5.15f. Dracontius(1914) provides a similar association.
[xxxi] Horace’s (1994) Odes iii, 24.
[xxxii] O’Daly (1991).
[xxxiii] See Augustine, Confessions.
[xxxiv] O’Daly (1991), p. 180
[xxxv] Hesiod (1959).
[xxxvi] Lamberton (1988).
[xxxvii] Williams (1968), p. 587, lns 17-40.
[xxxviii] Ovid (1986), p. 5, 1.128f.
[xxxix] Ibid.
[xl] Williams (1962); Horace (1994, Ode III, 24).
[xli] Kelly (1884).
[xlii] Kallet (2001), p.4.
[xliii] Plutarch, Life of Crassus, ii, 1-6 In Langhorne and Langhorne (1893). See also Plutarch (1905).
[xliv] Earl (1967), p. 32.
[xlv] Hesiod (1959), p. 39, ln 177.
[xlvi] Propertius (1990), p. 275, Book 3 ln 7.
[xlvii] Plutarch (1905), p. 297.
[xlviii] ___________, p. 305.
[xlix] Berger and Luckmann (1966).
[l] Starik and Rands (1995), p. 909.
[li] Jennings and Zandbergen (1995), p. 1016.
[lii] Schmidheiny’s (1992).
[liii] Moore (1993).
[liv] Frederick (1992, 1995, 1998, 1999).
[lv] Frederick, (1992).
[lvi] Frederick (1992,1995).
[lvii] Frederick, (1995).
[lviii] Frederick, (1992).
[lix] Frederick, (1995).
[lx] Ibid.
[lxi] Hobbes (1996), p. 70.
[lxii] Frederick (1995), p. 92. For instance, potential innovations and economizing initiatives may be smothered by rank-order privilege behavior.
[lxiii] Bateson (1972).
[lxiv] Frederick (1995).
[lxv] Ophuls (1977), p. 25.
[lxvi] ___________, p. 13.
[lxvii] Bateson, (1972), p. 315.
[lxviii] Ophuls, (1977), p. 27.
[lxix] ____________, p. 30.
[lxx] ____________, p. 33.
[lxxi] Erdal et al. (1994).
[lxxii] Erdal et al. (1994), p. 179.
[lxxiii] Boehm, (1989); James, (1890), p. 429.
[lxxiv] Erdal et al. (1994), pp. 178, 181.
[lxxv] Jennings and Zandbergen (1995), p.1023.
[lxxvi] Frederick (1999).
[lxxvii] Frederick (1992).
[lxxviii] Frederick (1992), p. 43.
[lxxix] Frederick (1995).